Frequently Searched

Escaping the ICWA Penalty Box: In Defense of Equal Protection for Indian Children

September 12, 2017

Download the report here

Download the endnotes here

Introduction

In early 2016, a six-year-old Californian girl named “Lexi” was taken from the arms of her weeping foster parents, Rusty and Summer Page,1 and sent to live with her step-second-cousin in Utah instead. She had lived with the Pages for four years, after child welfare officials removed her from her drug-addicted mother and incarcerated father.2 Lexi had found love and stability in the Pages’ home. She thought of them as “mommy” and “daddy,” and regarded their other children as her siblings.3 Had this been an ordinary case, they would almost certainly have adopted her.

But Lexi was not like other children. Her great, great, great, great-grandparent was a full-blooded Choctaw Indian. That meant that foster-care and adoption proceedings in her case were governed by the Indian Child Welfare Act of 1978 (ICWA).ICWA gives tribal governments extraordinary power to control the fate of abused, neglected, or abandoned Indian children. It overrides the “best interests of the child” standard, hampers efforts to protect abused children, and imposes race-based restrictions on foster care or adoption of Indian kids.

ICWA was originally intended to prevent the breakup of Indian families and protect children and parents from abusive state officials.5 Laudable goals, to be sure. But in practice, ICWA often harms children by delaying or denying them placement in stable and loving homes, compelling their reunification with abusive birth parents, and mandating procedures that deprive them of the legal protections they need. In the most extreme cases, children who lack any cultural or political affiliation with a tribe, and do not live on a reservation, are subject to ICWA’s burdens solely because their ethnic ancestry renders them “eligible” for tribal membership.6 As the Supreme Court recently observed in Adoptive Couple v. Baby Girl—one of only two cases addressing ICWA—the Act’s mandates put Indian kids at “a unique disadvantage in finding . . . permanent and loving home[s],” and burden their futures “solely because an ancestor—even a remote one—was an Indian.”7

How is it possible that more than half a century after Brown v. Board of Education, the United States government still maintains a de jure “separate but equal”—or more precisely, separate and substandard—legal system for one racial group? What does it say about the basic principles of our Constitution vis-à-vis our Native American population? And how can this be fixed in a way that respects the legitimate interests of Indian tribes while protecting the most vulnerable Americans?

This article provides a brief overview of the origin and structure of ICWA, focusing on six provisions of the Act that place Indian children in “the ICWA Penalty Box” solely on account of their race. Because this article focuses primarily on cases involving children who do not live on reservations and have no cultural connection to tribes—but who are eligible for membership because of their genetic ancestry—not every argument presented here will be relevant to all ICWA proceedings.

But before beginning, a disclaimer is warranted. American Indian law is fraught with a bloody, tragic, often plainly disgusting history of racism, violence, and even genocide. That history—which played a prominent role in ICWA’s origin8—must not and cannot be ignored or treated euphemistically. This article is written in full recognition of the deplorable legacy of abuse and betrayal, mutual incomprehension and prejudice that has plagued relations between Indians and non-Indians in North America. It is tragic that these problems persist to this day—and that ICWA is partly to blame.

Though enacted with good intentions, the provisions of ICWA critiqued below harm Indian children, deprive them of the protection of the “best interests of the child” standard, move them beyond the reach of state protective services, curtail their rights to due process and equal protection, subordinate their interests to those of tribal governments, and cripple efforts to rescue them from abuse and find them stable homes. The “ICWA Penalty Box” obstructs the ability of American Indian children to realize the benefits of their American citizenship.

ICWA’s Background

This last point is worth emphasizing. All Indian children are citizens of the United States, and entitled to the equal protection of the laws.9 That they are denied such protection today is a disgrace. However noble the intentions behind ICWA’s passage, it is today often a cause of abuse. All children, regardless of their ancestry, deserve to be regarded as individuals, and their best interests should be the overriding consideration in cases involving their welfare. The United States owes American Indian children nothing less.

ICWA was enacted in response to efforts during the termination era to assimilate Indian children into American society. At that time, federal policy sought to separate Indian children from their parents10 and to place them in boarding schools, where many were abused and were punished for speaking Indian languages or practicing traditional religions. Children were also removed from Indian families under local standards that failed to account for traditional Indian cultural practices.

In passing ICWA, Congress sought to preserve and strengthen Indian families by preempting state child welfare laws that led to family breakup. Among other things, it gives tribal courts exclusive jurisdiction over child custody cases involving tribal members on reservations, orders state and federal courts to give full faith and credit to the child custody decisions of tribal courts,11 requires notification of parents and tribes regarding involuntary proceedings such as the severance of parental rights, mandates procedures to ensure that tribal members know their rights when asked to sign papers to terminate a parent-child relationship, and employs the “prevailing social and cultural standards of the Indian community” in child welfare cases.

Had ICWA stopped there, it would hardly be controversial. But it goes further—and falls short—in many other ways.

ICWA’s Basic Presumptions

The Rights of Parents, Tribes, and Children

The problems begin with the definition of an “Indian child.” Congress, understandably reluctant to interfere with the authority of tribes to determine their own membership, deferred wholesale to tribal authorities on the question of who qualifies as Indian for purposes of ICWA. The Act defines an “Indian child” as any child who is a member of a tribe, or is eligible for membership and is the biological child of a tribal member.12 Meanwhile, virtually all tribes define eligibility for membership in terms of ethnic heritage or ancestry. Federal regulations impose no minimum blood quantum.13 This means that a child can qualify as an Indian child for purposes of ICWA based on one drop of Indian blood.

The Cherokee Constitution, for example, defines eligibility solely based on whether a person has a direct ancestor on the Dawes Rolls.14 Other tribes define membership strictly by blood quantum. For example, Navajo law makes a person eligible for membership if he or she “is at least one-fourth degree Navajo blood.”15 Still other tribes require blood quantum but not tribal affiliation. Thus, the Gila River Indian Community entitles “all children of members . . . [who] are of at least one-fourth Indian blood” to membership.16 This means that, for instance, a child who is the child of a member but has only 1 percent Gila River ancestry and 24 percent Navajo ancestry is eligible for Gila River membership (but not Navajo citizenship) and is subject to ICWA. It also means that a child who is not biologically Indian but is fully connected to a tribe’s culture—say, the adopted child of a tribal member—is not subject to ICWA, while a child whose connection to a tribe is genetic is, even if that child has no cultural or social ties to the tribe.

Once a child qualifies as “an Indian child” under ICWA, the tribe’s authority with regard to that child is in many ways equal or even superior to the rights of the parents.17 Thus, even if parents wish to block application of ICWA, they are often unable to do so, and tribes can override the expressed wishes of parents.18 In Mississippi Band of Choctaw Indians v. Holyfield, Indian parents chose to leave the reservation before giving birth, and signed voluntary consent forms agreeing to have their child adopted by a non-Indian couple. Nevertheless, the tribe successfully moved to have the adoption order vacated for noncompliance with ICWA. The Supreme Court concluded that ICWA “was not meant to be defeated by the actions of individual members,” because the statute protects “not solely . . . Indian children and families, but also . . . tribes themselves.”19 In short, ICWA empowers tribal governments in ways that supersede the judgment of parents when the two come into conflict. As one Indian law expert says, “The purpose of ICWA . . . is ultimately to maintain the survival of the tribe through the retention of its members.”20

The idea of government elevating any third party to “parity” with the rights of parents is disturbing and unconstitutional. In Troxel v. Granville, the Supreme Court struck down a Washington state law that forced parents to let “any person” visit with their children whenever a court determined that this would be “in the best interest of the child,” even if it ran contrary to the parents’ preferences. Six justices found that parental rights, being fundamental rights, could only be infringed for extraordinarily important reasons, and that the Washington statute overrode those rights on too light a basis. Worse, the court suspected that other Washington courts were applying a presumption against parental choices: “In effect, the judge placed on . . . the fit custodial parent, the burden of disproving that visitation would be in the best interest of her daughters.” Given the fundamental status of parental rights, the Supreme Court ruled that parents’ choices must be accorded “special weight,” over and above the quotidian “best interests” standard.21

ICWA goes even further than the Washington visitation statute. It involves not mere visitation rights, but the far more intrusive matter of tribal jurisdiction to make operative decisions about child foster care, adoption, and other matters, even where those children are not domiciled on a reservation and are not members of tribes (but are only eligible for membership). It allows tribes to block adoption indefinitely while they seek foster and adoptive families of Native American ancestry, and to prohibit it entirely by mandating that children be placed in accordance with tribal preferences. ICWA promotes the interests of a tribe—nonfamily members—above the choices of parents, and does so not on the basis of a “best interests” determination—which, however unclear or “free-ranging”22 it might be, at least involves an assessment of a child’s unique needs.

The Best Interests of the Child

For centuries, the “best interests of the child” standard has been viewed as the essential lodestar for child welfare litigation.23 A judge must, in the words of Justice Benjamin Cardozo, “put himself in the position of a ‘wise affectionate and careful parent’ and make provision for the child accordingly.”24 Courts have called the best interests standard the “touchstone” and the “linchpin” of the law of child welfare.25 This standard is inherently individualized, meaning that it focuses on the particular interests of the specific child under his or her unique circumstances.26

ICWA deprives children whose ancestry is Indian of the protection of that rule and substitutes a uniform, often insurmountable presumption that it is in Indian children’s best interests to have their futures determined by tribal authorities. Some courts—and the BIA—have taken the position that this presumption overrides individualized consideration of the child’s personal best interests, except in the rarest circumstances.27 And this presumption does not depend on existing social or cultural links between child and tribe, but on the basis of biology. BIA regulations even impose a presumption that ICWA applies when a child is merely suspected of having Indian ancestry.28

ICWA’s presumptions also implicate the rights of parents. The rights of birth parents—particularly their fundamental right to direct the upbringing of their children—is violated when the government gives a third party rights over the child that are equal to or even greater than their own.29 ICWA also deprives non-Indian foster and adoptive parents of their right to a legal process that takes no regard of their race or nationality. Non-Indian adults seeking to adopt Indian children face a far greater burden in court, requiring a vast investment of time and money for legal representation. They also face a greater risk of losing their cases for reasons unrelated to their fitness as adoptive parents—simply because ICWA presumes—as Indian law expert N. Bruce Duthu expresses it—“that the [Indian] child’s best interests are served by maintaining his or her actual or even potential cultural and social links with his or her Indian tribe.”30

Blanket presumptions of this sort—even if rebuttable—raise significant due process concerns. In Stanley v. Illinois, the Supreme Court struck down a state law under which children of unmarried parents were taken into state custody upon the death of the mother, without any proof of neglect on the father’s part. “It may be . . . that most unmarried fathers are unsuitable and neglectful parents,” the court noted, “but all unmarried fathers are not in this category,” and a father should have a genuine opportunity to make his case based on his individual circumstances. “Procedure by presumption is always cheaper and easier than individualized determination,” declared the court, but when a legal presumption “forecloses the determinative issues of competence and care, when it explicitly disdains present realities in deference to past formalities, it needlessly risks running roughshod over the important interests of both parent and child.”31

Of course, a presumption in favor of a father can also run afoul of the “best interests standard.” In Dickason v. Sturdavan, the Arizona Supreme Court recognized that while a father may ordinarily be presumed to be the best caretaker of his child (because the “voice of nature, which declares that the father is the natural guardian of the minor child, cannot be silenced”), there may be cases in which fathers are unsuitable. Because the child’s welfare is the “paramount consideration,” a parent’s “prima facie right to . . . custody is not . . . unconditional.”32

ICWA’s presumptions are at least as powerful as those rejected in Stanley and Dickason. They categorically presume that Indian children are better off in Indian families, or in families selected by tribal governments, rather than with non-Indian families. That presumption compromises, and frequently subordinates, the welfare of children by focusing on the interests of tribal collectives. ICWA itself declares that there is “no resource that is more vital to the continued existence and integrity of Indian tribes than their children,” but while that may be true, there are cases in which the interests of tribes as corporate institutions conflict with the interests of children.

Where ICWA goes wrong is in its failure, in the event of such conflict, to unequivocally prioritize the latter. In Holyfield, the Supreme Court quoted the Utah Supreme Court’s rationale for ICWA’s equivocation between tribal interests and the interests of children: “[the] relationship between Indian tribes and Indian children domiciled on the reservation finds no parallel in other ethnic cultures,” it declared. “It is a relationship that many non-Indians find difficult to understand and that non-Indian courts are slow to recognize.” But the Utah court supported its assertion, not by reference to any unique needs of Indian children, but instead by reference to the tribe’s interest in sovereignty. Specifically, it cited two cases that emphasized the role that tribal jurisdiction over child custody cases plays in ensuring tribal autonomy: “if tribal sovereignty is to have any meaning at all,” it concluded, “it must necessarily include the right, within its own boundaries and membership, to provide for the care and upbringing of its young, a sine qua non to the preservation of its identity.”33

All of that may be true, but it is also irrelevant to the question of whether Indian children as individual persons have special needs that justify a legal presumption that they are themselves better off in the hands of tribal authorities. It may be the case that the authority to adjudicate custody disputes on reservations is a sine qua non of tribal sovereignty, but it simply does not follow that this is in the best interests of the children themselves—or that ICWA’s means of achieving the preservation of tribes is compatible with the due process rights of children and parents. Holyfield simply never addressed that subject.

This blindness to the best interests of Indian children is plain from ICWA’s opening phrases. The Act defines Indian children as tribal “resources” to be regulated in such a manner as to achieve “the continued existence and integrity of Indian tribes.”34 But Indian children are not resources, they are persons— citizens of the United States—and it is improper for government to treat any individual, least of all a citizen, as a means to achieve some third party’s ends.

While the United States has a trust obligation to respect and protect tribal sovereignty, it does not follow that an American citizen may be legally segregated based on Indian ancestry, or may be regarded as a member of a separate legal class based on national origin, or may be subordinated to the federal government’s interests in benefitting another corporate or government entity.35 Indeed, such a proposition is fundamentally incompatible with the proposition that all men are created equal. The preservation of tribes as political and cultural units is simply not adequate justification for imposing legal presumptions that deprive children of their constitutional rights.

ICWA and Social Science

ICWA’s powerful presumptions are often defended on the grounds that Indian children suffer unique psychological damage when they are placed in non-Indian households, or even that the feelings of attachment that Indian children experience is qualitatively different from those that non-Indian children experience.36 Support for such claims is dubious at best. For instance, one well-known 2000 report entitled Split Feathers argued that Indian children adopted into non-Indian homes face a higher risk of alcoholism, social disability, and other psychological problems, and are likely to express feelings of alienation and a loss of identity.37 Perhaps there are such cases, but Split Feathers cannot withstand scholarly scrutiny. It was confessedly unscientific, based on only twenty informal interviews of adults, and it drew untenable causal conclusions based on correlation. For instance, it did not seek to determine whether the problems it identified might have resulted from abuses that subjects experienced before they were removed from their birth families, or from the discrimination that Indians may face in white society, as opposed to the fact of adoption itself. It is impossible to know for sure what role these factors played, because the report indicated no control group, was not peer-reviewed, and the author did not disclose her methodology.38 Other surveys suffer from similar flaws.39 More reliable evidence supports the proposition that cross-ethnic adoption is good for children, or at least does not harm them.40

Even if there were scientific support for the proposition that Indian children are better off when placed with other Indians, it is doubtful that ICWA properly addresses that problem. For one thing, neither the Act nor its implementing regulations apply to tribal court proceedings.41 This means that tribal courts can, and do, approve foster and adoption placements with non-Indian households. If ICWA is intended to protect Indian children from the allegedly unique injury of being placed with families of other ethnicities, it would make no sense to allow such placements simply because tribal courts order them. Nor does ICWA apply to divorce proceedings, even though divorces frequently involve child custody. State courts can therefore award custody of an Indian child to a non-Indian parent in a divorce proceeding without triggering ICWA—which, again, would be irrational if the Act were aimed at preventing an alleged psychological harm suffered by Indian children being raised by non-Indians.

Some writers have argued that the psychological needs of Indian children are qualitatively different from the needs of non-Indian children. One argues that a child’s need for a feeling of household stability and permanency “is a malleable concept,” and that Indian children experience permanency “in [their] tie to the native community and the cultural practices of that community,” as opposed to permanency in a stable, loving home. Thus, placing an Indian child in the custody of a family of another race “is not the type of ‘permanency” they need.42

It is doubtful that Indian children inherently have a categorically different psychological experience of permanency than do children with different genes—one that inherently turns on tribal links—but even if it were true, ICWA does not rationally address such concerns. Its adoption and foster placement preferences make no reference to culture or tribe, thereby encouraging adoption of Indian children by “other Indian families” 43 even if they are of entirely different tribal cultural backgrounds. These preferences can also be invoked to override the preferences of Native parents, and by non-Indian birth parents to bar adoptions of which tribal member birthparents approve.44 And the fact that ICWA does not apply in tribal court means that tribal judges can, and sometimes do, override children’s “ties to the native community” and place those children with non-Indian families. In any event, the notion that Indian children suffer uniquely when they are placed with adoptive families of non-Indian cultural backgrounds cannot justify applying ICWA to off-reservation children who have no pre-existing cultural connection to a tribe. A child like Lexi, whose only connection to a tribe is biological, has no cultural ties to preserve—unless, of course, she is to be regarded as biologically different, and consequently destined for a segregated legal regime due to her genetics.

How the ICWA Penalty Box Works

ICWA includes six provisions that diverge significantly from the rules that apply to non-Indian children in foster care and adoption proceedings. These are: (1) jurisdictional rules that mandate transfer of child welfare cases to tribal court and give tribes rights as parties to these cases on a par with the rights of parents; (2) the “active efforts” requirement that essentially requires child welfare workers to return children to the custody of unfit birth parents; (3) the “clear and convincing evidence” standard that it makes applicable in foster care cases; (4) the “beyond a reasonable doubt” standard that states must apply in termination of parental rights cases; (5) race-based foster and pre-adoptive placement preferences; and (6) race-based adoptive placement preferences. Together, these provisions create “the ICWA penalty box”—a set of legal disadvantages that make it harder to protect Indian children from abuse, and to find them permanent adoptive homes.45

Tribal Jurisdiction and Intervention Powers

ICWA gives tribal governments extensive power over cases involving children who are not tribal members and are not domiciled on reservations. Specifically, it requires state courts (in the absence of either parental objection or “good cause” to deviate from ICWA’s mandates) to transfer foster care and termination-of-parental-rights proceedings to the courts of the child’s tribe, to be determined there.46 The 2015 BIA Guidelines apply this rule to all stages of custody proceedings, including pre-adoption (guardianship) and adoption proceedings.47 Parents can block the transfer of foster or termination cases to tribal court, but ICWA also gives tribal governments power to intervene as parties in such proceedings anywhere in the nation if they involve Indian children.48 Also, if a tribe learns after the fact that a state court decided an adoption matter without tribal involvement, the tribe is entitled to reopen the proceedings and have them nullified.49

Tribal jurisdiction over children of Indian parents on reservations seems an unremarkable example of in personam and territorial jurisdiction.50 Holyfield read this authority broadly, to encompass children born to tribal members who left the reservation to give birth, on the grounds that such an act does not change the domicile of a person who is in all other respects domiciled on the reservation.51 This, too, was unremarkable; the law of domicile is commonplace in personal jurisdiction law, and immigration law for children born to expatriate parents employs this rule.52 But ICWA’s jurisdictional provisions go much further. Its jurisdiction-transfer provision applies to any case anywhere in the country that involves a child eligible for tribal membership, even if not domiciled on a reservation, and even where no party to the case has any significant contact with the tribe beyond biology. This conflicts with basic jurisdictional principles required by due process of law.

Due process requires that before a court adjudicates a dispute, there must be “contacts” between the forum jurisdiction and the defendant “such that [the defendant] should reasonably anticipate being summoned to court there.”53 Due process of law simply “does not contemplate” that a court “may make binding a judgment in personam against an individual” who has “no contacts, ties, or relations” to that court’s jurisdiction.54 Where a person has “carr[ied] on no activity whatsoever” in the forum jurisdiction, and has “avail[ed] [himself] of none of the privileges and benefits of [the forum’s] law,” then the forum state cannot exercise jurisdiction because there are no “affiliating circumstances” that would satisfy the requirements of “fair play and substantial justice.”55

ICWA’s grant of nationwide jurisdiction over proceedings involving children with only a biological connection to a tribe plainly exceeds these limits. A child who is merely born eligible for tribal membership—that is, who has the requisite genetic ancestry— has not thereby purposefully availed herself of any privileges of tribal law. One cannot “purposefully avail” oneself of one’s ethnicity. Nor have that child’s foster or would-be adoptive parents engaged in conduct in connection with the tribal forum such that tribal jurisdiction satisfies fair play and substantial justice. One could hardly imagine, say, a Virginia court asserting personal jurisdiction over a child welfare proceeding in California on the grounds that the child’s ancestors came from Virginia, or parents came from Virginia, or that the child was conceived in Virginia. Yet that is essentially the nationwide jurisdiction that ICWA gives to tribes.

Congress’s trust obligation to preserve tribal sovereignty cannot excuse ICWA from the mandates of due process and equal protection. However “plenary” Congress’s powers with regard to Indians are “‘not absolute’” and cannot trump the Constitution.56 Nobody would contend, for example, that the trust obligation to preserve tribal sovereignty would entitle Congress to, say, forbid Indians from relinquishing tribal membership, or leaving reservations, or marrying non-Indians, or obtaining abortions.57 All these things would help increase and strengthen tribal membership but Congress’s powers with regard to its trust obligation are limited by the Constitution, and particularly by constitutional protections for the rights of American citizens.

As in all cases, personal jurisdiction in ICWA cases must satisfy the requirements of due process, including the “minimum contacts/purposeful availment” analysis.58 Yet while the minimum contacts requirement is certainly satisfied when a tribal court exercises jurisdiction over tribal members domiciled on the reservation, that requirement is not satisfied in cases involving off-reservation children whose sole connection to a tribe is their biological ancestry.

Federalism and the Role of States

ICWA’s interference with state court jurisdiction also collides with principles of federalism. There is typically no disputing the federal government’s power to preempt states with regard to Indian law, but such preemption is problematic when it is stretched to include off-reservation matters involving children who are not members of a tribe, but only eligible for membership for biological reasons. Family law is quintessentially a subject of state concern, left to the purview of the states by the Tenth Amendment.59 So great is the role of states in this area that federal courts even lack authority to decide divorce or child custody cases in diversity jurisdiction.60 Primary responsibility for family law is with the states, subject to the limits of federal constitutional protections.

But ICWA overrides state jurisdiction over family law, and dictates substantive law that state officials must implement in family law cases. In doing so, it disrupts what would otherwise be the uniform application of state law relating to foster care, custody, or adoption, without regard to race, ethnicity, or national origin. ICWA overrides this nondiscriminatory state law, and segregates “Indian children” into a special category subject to different rules, solely as a consequence of their ethnicity.

In United States v. Windsor, the Supreme Court held the federal Defense of Marriage Act unconstitutional in part because it interfered with state family law and mandated discrimination where none would have applied otherwise. Many states had chosen to broaden the definition of marriage to include same-sex couples, the Court noted, but the Defense of Marriage Act “intrude[d] on state power” and forced states to discriminate against same-sex couples. By imposing separate legal treatment where state law would ordinarily have applied a non-discriminatory rule, the Act “disrupt[ed] the federal balance.”61 The same is true of ICWA. It subjects children whose ethnic ancestry renders them eligible for tribal membership to unequal treatment, and overrides non-discriminatory state law in a way that makes it harder to ensure their safety and to find them adoptive homes.

True, ICWA was intended in part to remedy past discrimination, and Congress has power to override state law when necessary for this purpose. But such intervention imposes current burdens and must be justified by current needs.62 Whatever need there may have been a generation ago for federal intervention to protect American Indians from abuses at the hands of state child protection agencies, that cannot justify the continued intrusion on state law matters without some showing that those abuses remain, and that ICWA resolves them in a constitutionally acceptable manner.63

ICWA violates another essential protection for federalism, also. The federal government may not commandeer state officers or state legislatures,64 or require that they enforce federal law. In Printz v. United States, the Supreme Court found the Brady Act of 1993 unconstitutional because it “direct[ed] state law enforcement officers to participate, albeit only temporarily, in the administration of a federally enacted regulatory scheme.” People selling firearms were required to submit information forms to these officers so that background checks could be performed. Notably, the Act instructed officers to “make a reasonable effort” to determine whether a proposed firearm purchase was legal. If an officer determined that a sale would violate the law, the Act required the officer to give the would-be buyer a written explanation. If the purchase was legal, the officer was instructed to destroy the paperwork.65

Like the Brady Act, ICWA commands not only state judges but also state executive officers to participate in the administration of a federal regulatory program—one that overrides the quintessential state-law realm of family law. Among other things, ICWA orders state child welfare officers to place children in foster care or adoptive families in conformity with its preferences,66 mandates state record-keeping and inspection practices,67 and requires that state officers make “active efforts” to reunite Indian families— which includes “provid[ing] remedial services and rehabilitative programs” to abusive parents.68 In striking down the Brady Act, the Printz Court was particularly troubled by the Act’s “reasonable efforts” provision, noting that it essentially compelled states to adopt compliant policies, and “‘dragooned’” state officers “into administering federal law.”69 ICWA does precisely this—commanding not only that states adopt and implement “active efforts” policies, but also that they comply with the administration of a federally-mandated body of family law.

The recent BIA Guidelines are even more express in directly commanding state courts. They use the word “must” 101 times while instructing state agencies and officers. The Guidelines are meant to “clarify the minimum Federal standards, and best practices . . . to ensure that ICWA is applied in all States consistent with the Act’s express language,”70 and include instructions such as: “The agency seeking a[n] . . . adoptive . . . placement of an Indian child must always follow the placement preferences.”71 State courts often insist that the Guidelines are not mandatory,72 but they are certainly phrased in mandatory language.

In The Federalist, Alexander Hamilton thought it so hard to imagine the federal government trying “by some forced constructions of its authority” to “vary the [state] law” relating to inheritance or other domestic matters that only the “imprudent zeal” of the Constitution’s opponents could envision such a thing.73 Yet with ICWA, Congress has not only varied the law of child welfare for one specific ethnic group, but has compelled state officials to develop and implement a special set of standards that deviates from the state-law norm—often in ways that harm children.

“Active Efforts” to Reunify Families

ICWA differs from state law in many ways, with the result that Indian children are treated differently than children of other ethnicities in cases that are otherwise the same. Given that this law deals with the welfare of abused or neglected children, these differences can have a profound impact on the lives of America’s most vulnerable citizens.

Among the most significant of these differences involve efforts to reunify families after children have been taken into state custody. State law, as well as the federal Adoption and Safe Families Act,74 requires that child-welfare officials make “reasonable efforts” to reunify families in such cases.75 But the rules are different for Indian children: in their cases, state officials must make “active efforts” toward reunification.76 Although some state courts regard these terms as synonymous,77 most have concluded that “active efforts” imposes a greater obligation on the government to reunite children with families after a removal than does the “reasonable efforts” standard.78 The BIA’s Guidelines take this position,79 although its new regulations make no explicit determination.80

As a practical matter, the difference can be enormous. “Active efforts” is typically distinguished from “passive efforts,” such as making counseling services or similar opportunities available for parents who wish to reunify their families. While that might satisfy the “reasonable efforts” standard, it is insufficient to discharge a state’s duties under ICWA’s active efforts mandate.81 Instead, ICWA requires state social services workers to positively assist in developing parenting skills, obtaining employment, or whatever else the parent must have to retain custody, even if the parent shows little progress or even demonstrates a lack of interest.

The “active efforts” requirement is a delicate balance. “Reunification” of the family might mean the restoration of normal relationships after a bad episode in the family’s history. Or it can mean returning a child to a known abusive family where the child will suffer repeated instances of abuse or neglect. ICWA’s “active efforts” provision is so poorly designed that it often has the perverse effect of exposing Indian children to a greater risk of abuse or neglect, and frequently results in delaying or denying protection that the child needs.

Most courts have ruled that because ICWA’s active efforts requirement is more stringent than “reasonable efforts,” the circumstances that would ordinarily relieve the state of the obligation to reunite the family under the “reasonable efforts” standard do not relieve the state of the obligation to make active efforts.82 This means that while officials are not required to reunify a non-Indian child with a family after she is removed due to parental substance-abuse problems, or physical or sexual abuse,83 such a duty does exist with regard to Indian children. Even incarceration of the parent does not relieve state child welfare workers of their duty to actively seek reunification of Indian children and birth parents.84 The BIA’s recently announced Guidelines expand the active efforts requirement, mandating that state officials prove beyond a reasonable doubt that active efforts have been unsuccessful, and prove this through the testimony of an expert witness who is an expert in the culture and customs of the child’s tribe (as opposed to an expert on child welfare or child psychology).85 And the BIA’s 2016 regulations provide that the “active efforts” requirement must apply as soon as state officers have “reason to know”—often merely a suspicion—that a child is subject to ICWA.86

The Supreme Court held in 2013 that “active efforts” are not required in cases where the birth parent has never had contact with the child, in which case there is no Indian family threatened with breakup.87 But the “active efforts” requirement may be more problematic in cases where the birth parent has had contact, because in such cases, that requirement can force state officials to return children to the very parents who have abused them in the first place.

One example of this is In re Interest of Shayla H., in which Nebraska child welfare officials removed three children, Shayla (12), Shania (11), and Tanya (9) from their birth father, David, due to allegations of physical abuse. Specifically, Shayla had been beaten by David’s girlfriend, Danielle (not the children’s mother), and child welfare officials found that all three were suffering from neglect. Shania and Tanya were enrolled members of the Sioux tribe, and although Shayla was not, she was eligible for membership. The children were returned to the family, and over the next seven months, David and Danielle participated in counseling services geared toward reunification. However, the children showed signs of continuing problems. The trial court concluded that it was in their best interests that custody remain with state social services, although they were physically returned to the couple. The court also required David to cooperate with state child welfare investigations, to desist from physical discipline of the children, to provide them with therapy, etc.

The Appellate Court reversed, on the grounds that although the state had employed “reasonable” efforts at reunifying the children with David, it had not employed active efforts. The trial court’s finding that the children’s best interests would be best served by the state retaining legal custody was therefore insufficient.88 The Nebraska Supreme Court agreed, holding that even though the children remained in the birth parent’s physical custody, the decision to withhold legal custody fell short of the active efforts requirement.

Only briefly mentioned in the court’s opinion was the fact that “the children were subsequently removed from David’s physical custody.”89 That was because by the time the court ruled, David had once again abused the three, as well as other children. In May, 2015, the Juvenile Court found him “unfit by reason of debauchery or repeated lewd and lascivious behavior” and “callous disregard for those children’s emotional well-being.” David, a methamphetamine addict, had molested Danielle’s son and daughter as well as his own youngest daughter, and had failed to protect the three from sexual molestation by Danielle’s sons. The court concluded that all three girls had “experienced lifetimes of trauma.”90 Had the courts applied the best interests standard as the overriding consideration from the outset—and had state officials not been required to make “active efforts” to reunite Shayla, Shania, and Tanya with their abusive father—much needless suffering could have been avoided.

Even in less extreme circumstances, ICWA’s “active efforts” provision inflicts unnecessary psychological harm on children. In Department of Human Services v. J.M., the Oregon Court of Appeals affirmed a trial court’s decision to clear a child, referred to as L, for adoption. The case began in 2009, when state officials removed L’s sibling from the birth parents on the basis of neglect. That sibling was eventually adopted. Three years later, L was born, and child welfare workers sought to take him into custody two days after his birth. The parents were diagnosed with mental and emotional problems, as well as anger management and aggression problems, but because L was an Indian child, ICWA’s “active efforts” mandate applied.

Thus, in late 2012, the state presented the parents with rehabilitation and treatment plans requiring counseling, parenting classes, and regular visits with L. But the parents  skipped sessions, paid little attention to the classes, and had repeated emotional outbursts, including storming out of an anger management session. Nevertheless, the state persisted in its efforts throughout 2013. The parents were frequently uncooperative, and the counseling sessions, conducted with L present, often ended in tension and frustration. “At a June session,” the court later found, “father used abusive language and behavior towards [the counselor] in L’s presence; neither parent recognized how such behavior could be frightening for L.” The father’s “explosive behavior and inappropriate language” had led the counselor to terminate other sessions, all leading to greater anxiety and delay,91 but the state continued its efforts. Only after 18 months of persistent failures of this sort did the trial court rule that L could be removed from the parents and placed in foster care. The parents then appealed, and the court of appeals rendered its decision ten months later, in October of 2014. A petition to the state Supreme Court followed, and was not denied until February 2015, when L was four years old.92

ICWA’s “active efforts” requirement returns abused children to the custody of abusive adults, forces children to experience the strain of parents’ psychological or social problems to a greater degree than other children must experience under the “reasonable efforts” rule, increases the stress on foster families, prolongs the adoption process, and encourages unnecessary technical appeals.93 Courts in California—one of only two states to embrace the proposition that “active efforts” does not apply when parents prove unfit— have observed that ICWA “was not intended as a shield to permit abusive treatment of Indian children by their parents.”94 But in practice, that frequently happens.

Different Burdens of Proof for Foster Care and Termination of Parental Rights

In cases involving non-Indian children, the decision to place a child in foster care is made by employing such burdens of proof as “reasonable grounds,” or “probable cause,” or “preponderance of the evidence.” These standards strike a balance between the rights of parents not to lose custody on too light a basis, and the rights of children not to be left in an abusive household simply because officers have been unable to gather definitive evidence. Arizona law, for example, allows state officials to remove a child from an abusive home in an emergency and place that child in temporary foster care if “reasonable grounds exist to believe that temporary custody is clearly necessary to protect the child,” and “probable cause exists to believe” that the child is suffering or will imminently suffer abuse, neglect, or serious emotional injury.95 Arizona law also uses a “preponderance of evidence” standard in determining dependency—i.e., placing children in long-term foster care.96

In Santosky v. Kramer, the Supreme Court employed the “clear and convincing evidence” standard, finding that anything less demanding would violate the due process rights of parents—their interests are too significant to be disposed of on a mere preponderance-of-the-evidence standard. But the Court also declined to adopt the “beyond-a-reasonable-doubt” requirement because the type of psychological evidence relied upon in family law cases is not usually susceptible of proof beyond a reasonable doubt, and such a demanding rule might “erect an unreasonable barrier to state efforts to free permanently neglected children for adoption.”97 This is important because termination is often necessary to clear the way for permanent adoption.98

ICWA disregards this warning, however, and imposes heavier burdens of proof in cases involving Indian children. In order to place an Indian child in foster care, the state must prove by clear and convincing evidence—as opposed to reasonable grounds or probable cause—that allowing the child to remain in the parent’s custody “is likely to result in serious emotional or physical damage to the child,” and such a funding must be based on expert testimony.99 And in cases involving termination of parental rights, ICWA imposes the beyond a reasonable doubt standard that the Santosky Court rejected. These different burdens mean that “caseworkers and attorneys are sometimes reluctant to accept surrenders of, or terminate parental rights to, an Indian child,”100 even where that would be in the best interest of the child. Obtaining expert testimony is costly for social services agencies operating on limited budgets and staff.101 Requiring proof of serious physical damage is also likely to delay the removal of children from dangerous situations.

One distressingly common fact pattern in cases involving termination (as well as “active efforts”) occurs when the parents of an Indian child separate, and the mother remarries. When her new husband seeks to adopt her child as his own, the ex-husband can use ICWA to block what would otherwise be the formation of a stable new family. This is not only contrary to the child’s best interests, but to the wishes of Indian parents themselves.

For example, In re Adoption of T.A.W.102 involved a child born in 2007 to C.B., a member of the Shoalwater Bay Tribe, and a non-Indian birth father, C.W. C.W., a methamphetamine addict, had what the trial court later called a “significant criminal history,” including convictions for drug possession, car theft, fleeing the police, and burglary.103 When, in 2012, he was released from prison, C.B. obtained a protective order against him from the Shoalwater tribal court. It ordered C.W. to undergo six months of domestic violence classes before he could visit with the child.104

C.B. met and married another man, R.B.—an Indian—in June, 2013. C.W. was back in prison by then, this time to serve two years for robbery.105 C.B. and R.B. then asked a state court to terminate his parental rights, preparatory to R.B. adopting the child as his own. The tribe supported this move, and the trial court found beyond a reasonable doubt that the requirements of ICWA were satisfied. But the Court of Appeals disagreed. It found insufficient evidence “that active efforts were made to provide C.W. with remedial services and rehabilitative programs to prevent the breakup of the Indian family.” The fact that C.W. was not an Indian was irrelevant, the court found, because “the plain language of ICWA states that its provisions apply to the termination of parental rights to an Indian child without regard to a parent’s status.”106 In short, despite plentiful reason for concluding that C.W. was an unfit parent, despite the fact that he chose to absent himself from his child’s life, despite the best judgment of both the Indian mother and her tribe, and despite the fact that ICWA was operating in this case to interfere with the Indian parent’s choices, contrary to the wishes of the tribe, and in service of the non-Indian birth parent, the court barred the termination (and consequent adoption) because the parties had not made “timely and diligent efforts” to “engag[e] the parent . . . in reasonably available and culturally appropriate preventive, remedial, or rehabilitative services.”107 The Washington Supreme Court affirmed. “[W]hether the parent whose rights are being terminated is non-Indian is immaterial,” it found.108 One dissenting justice pointed out the absurdity of this outcome: “Indian child T.A.W. is in an Indian home with his Indian natural mother and with an Indian stepfather with whom T.A.W. has bonded.”109 To allow a non-Indian to bar that adoption under a statute intended to prevent the breakup of Indian families is nonsensical.

In In re Custody of S.E.G., the Minnesota Supreme Court reversed a trial court’s finding that three Indian children were better off in the custody of their non-Indian foster parents. Social services removed the children from the birth parents when one was four, another three, and another one year old, and were placed in foster care. Over the three years that followed, they were moved six times before being placed with the non-Indian couple, E.C. and C.C., in 1991. A year later, the children were placed with an Indian family, but that only lasted nine days, before they were returned to E.C. and C.C. Therapists who met with the children emphasized their need for permanent family bonds, particularly one special-needs child. After another year of searching, the tribe was unable to locate an Indian family willing to adopt the three, but E.C. and C.C. were willing, and nobody disputed their fitness. In its adoption proceeding, the trial court received evidence from both lay and expert witnesses, all of whom testified that the couple were providing for the children’s physical, emotional, and intellectual needs, but who disagreed as to whether they were providing for the children’s “cultural needs.” E.C. and C.C. attended powwows and tribal story-tellings, and even arranged a Chippewa naming ceremony for one child. But in any event, the expert witnesses testified that the most important thing was for the children to find stable and secure homes.

Nevertheless, the Minnesota Supreme Court overruled this concern and reversed the trial court’s adoption order. It found that the expert witnesses E.C. and C.C. offered were not qualified experts specifically on Indian tribal culture and childrearing practices, which meant their testimony was insufficient to support a beyond-a-reasonable-doubt finding that the children’s “cultural needs” were being met. Thus, although nobody disputed that adoption was in the children’s best interests, the court found that the best interests standard was improper under ICWA because it is “imbued with the values of majority culture,” as opposed to Indian culture.110

Whether or not these cases are correctly interpreted ICWA, these cases demonstrate how the Act’s “beyond a reasonable doubt” test delays the removal of children from abusive or neglectful families, and can even force the return of abused children to the very people who abused them—simply because the evidence of abuse is “only” clear and convincing. As Christine D. Bakeis observes, in a classic example of understatement, “[s]uch a result is clearly not beneficial to children with Indian ancestry.”111

Foster, Pre-adoptive and Adoption Placement Preferences

When state courts review potential adoptions of Indian children, or consider placing them in foster care (or what ICWA calls “pre-adoptive placement”), those courts must abide by a hierarchy of race-based placement preferences.

In a foster or pre-adoptive placement, a state court must give preference to members of the extended family (as defined by tribal custom);112 if none are available, to a foster home approved or specified by the tribe; if none are available, to an Indian foster home approved by a non-Indian authority; and, again, if none are available, to an institution approved by an Indian tribe or an Indian organization.113 In adoption cases, the court must give preference first to a member of the child’s extended family (as defined by the tribe); second, to other members of the child’s tribe; and, lastly, to “other Indian families.”114

These placement preferences are based on race, not political or tribal affiliation.115 The foster care preferences mandate that a child be sent to “an Indian” foster facility approved by “an Indian tribe”—not the child’s own tribe—and the adoption preference hierarchy gives preference to “other Indian families” over non-Indians who wish to adopt, even if those families are of a different tribe.116 It is thus not tribal membership that matters, but generic Indianness. As if that were not enough, the federal Multi-Ethnic Placement Act forbids the denial or delay of an adoption or custody proceeding on the basis of race—but it specifically excludes one group of children from this protection: Indian children.117

Ranking would-be foster and adoptive families in terms of ancestry rather than in terms of the children’s best interests is bound to cause problems, and severe problems have indeed resulted. Shortly after their birth in 2010, Laurynn Whiteshield and her twin sister Michaela were removed from their parents and placed with a non-Indian foster family in Bismarck, North Dakota. When county officials sought to terminate parental rights, however, the Spirit Lake Sioux tribe invoked ICWA and had the case transferred to tribal court, which ordered that the children be placed with their grandfather, Freeman Whiteshield, on the Spirit Lake Reservation, despite the fact that Freeman’s wife, Hope Whiteshield, had a record of child neglect charges. A month later, Hope grew angry at the twins while they were playing outside, and threw them down an embankment. Laurynn died from the head trauma, and Hope was sentenced to thirty years in prison. Michaela was returned to the custody of the non-Indian family from whom she had originally been taken.118

Even where there is no such abuse, ICWA’s foster and adoption preference scheme imposes unnecessary suffering on children who are denied stability and sometimes taken away from homes where they feel safe and loved. This often happens in ways that do not even preserve tribal cultural integrity.

That was true in the case involving Lexi, the six-year-old Choctaw girl in California who was removed from the foster family where she had lived for four years and sent to live with her father’s step-second cousins in Utah. Lexi (short for Alexandria) was born in December, 2009, to a mother addicted to methamphetamine, who had lost custody of at least six children before Lexi’s birth.119 Her father had an extensive criminal history. He was not aware that he was an enrolled member of the Choctaw tribe until after Lexi’s placement in foster care, and had no cultural ties to the tribe.120 Nevertheless, Lexi was subject to ICWA. For four years, she thrived in the Pages’ care, came to call them “mommy” and “daddy,” and to regard their other children as her siblings, and California courts deemed the Pages her “de facto parents.” The “active efforts” to reunify Lexi with her father collapsed in 2012 when the father, having been released from prison, decided he was no longer interested in reunification. At that point, the tribe deemed Lexi’s step-second cousins to be “extended family” thanks to their relationship to Lexi’s now-deceased grandmother. The step-second cousins, however, had no Native ancestry, and were not tribal members. Nor was there any evidence that they were familiar with Choctaw culture or that placing Lexi with them would ensure that she was exposed to Choctaw tradition.

The Pages urged the court to find “good cause” to deviate from the ICWA placement preferences. Nobody disputed that the Pages were outstanding parents. Rather, the “good cause” hearing focused on the psychological trauma Lexi would experience if she were removed from their care. Although witnesses testified that she had a strong bond with the Pages and would suffer extreme distress at being separated from them, the trial court nevertheless ordered her removal because the testimony “did not reach to the level of certainty that Alexandria would suffer extreme detriment.” It found that Lexi would likely recover from the experience of being removed from the Pages, and that the extent of her bond with them did not supersede ICWA’s placement mandates.

The Court of Appeal reversed, admonishing the trial court for requiring definitive certainty of psychological damage before deviating from ICWA, and instructing the trial court to consider Lexi’s individual best interests and the extent of her bond with the Pages.121 After contentious efforts to obtain evidence regarding Lexi’s bond with the Pages, the trial court, in November of 2015, ordered Lexi removed from the Pages and placed with the Utah family. The Court of Appeal promptly vacated that order on the grounds that the trial court had not complied with the terms of remand.122 Four months later, the trial court held another hearing—after refusing to receive new evidence—and again ruled against the Pages. On the morning of Sunday, March 20, 2016, after Lexi had lived with the Pages for four years and three months, she was taken from them and driven away to Utah. The psychological trauma inflicted by separating Lexi from the Pages’ stable and loving home after four years can only have been extreme.123

The Pages appealed, arguing that the removal was contrary to Lexi’s best interests, but the California Court of Appeal affirmed. It did not refuse outright to apply the best interests standard, but purported to apply a different kind of best interests standard. “When the best interests of an Indian child are being considered,” it declared, courts “should take an Indian child’s best interests into account as one of the constellation of factors.”124 For children of other races, of course, the child’s best interest is the overriding consideration, and in cases in which children have spent long periods in foster care, California courts typically regard the child’s need for stability as the deciding factor.125

“When the best interests of an Indian child are being considered,” the court continued, “the importance of preserving the child’s . . . cultural connections often cannot be separated from other factors.”126 This statement makes no sense. Lexi had no cultural connection to the Choctaw tribe; her connection to the tribe was only biological. It was on account of her biological status that the court viewed her individual interests as only one of the “constellation” of factors by which her future would be determined.127

As the Whiteshield and Lexi cases, and countless others, demonstrate, ICWA prioritizes ethnic criteria above the individualized consideration of their best interests—to the detriment of children and the adults who love them.

ICWA’s Foster and Adoption Preferences Deprive Indian Children of Due Process, Equal Protection, and Freedom of Association Rights

ICWA’s placement preferences deprive Indian children of their rights to due process, equal protection, and freedom of association.

One of the most basic elements of due process of law128 is that courts must address the specific facts at issue in a case,129 and issue individualized judgments rather than impose blanket assumptions premised on a person’s race, national origin, or other “immutable characteristic[s] determined solely by the accident of birth.”130 Yet in an ICWA case, the most crucial factor—virtually the deciding factor—is the child’s biologically-determined Indian status. ICWA’s race-based foster and adoption preferences deprive children of the individualized consideration inherent in due process, and because these preferences result in treating them differently than other children due exclusively to their racial or national origin, they also deprive Indian children of the equal protection of the law.

In addition, ICWA’s preferences violate the First Amendment freedom of association. Tribal membership and family relationships are both forms of association protected by the First Amendment.131 The right to associate includes the right not to associate.132 Minors have First Amendment rights, including the right not to associate.133 Yet ICWA tries to force the formation of tribal and even familial bonds by essentially compelling children to join Indian families based on their biological ancestry, irrespective of their individual best interests. BIA regulations even require state officers to enroll children in tribes if they are not already enrolled.134 Thus even putting aside the question (discussed below) of whether ICWA establishes a political or a racial classification, the Act’s placement preferences are unconstitutional.

The First Amendment forbids government from mandating that people join political associations,135 make political statements,136 or pledge allegiance to the government.137 But ICWA seeks to force one specific class of American citizens to obtain formal membership in a political unit that enjoys attributes of sovereignty. Tribal membership is not ordinary dual citizenship, of course, given the “unique and limited”138 nature of tribal sovereignty, but tribal membership significantly changes the legal regime that applies to a person,139 because it “denotes an association with the polity” and imposes an “unequivocal legal bond.”140 A person with dual nationality can be “subject to claims from both nations, claims which at times may be competing or conflicting.”141 The government may not force one group of citizens, defined by ancestry, to obtain citizenship from another sovereign and thereby submit to a change in his legal rights and obligations.

Even more intrusively, ICWA seeks to create Indian families through its preferences as well as through its “active efforts” provision. Freedom of association, a fundamental aspect of individual liberty, includes family relationships, because these are intimate and “involve deep attachments and commitments” to those “few” others with whom one shares “a special community of thoughts, experiences, and beliefs” and the “distinctively personal aspects of one’s life.”142 Yet ICWA endeavors to force the formation of family bonds by mandating adoption of Indian children by “other Indian families,” and also obstructs the formation of consensual family bonds between Indian children and non-Indian adoptive families. The decision to form a family is entitled to legal protection,143 yet ICWA can override that choice even where birth parents and fit adoptive families (and even children themselves)144 would prefer to form an adoptive family outside the racial categories ICWA imposes. For the state to interfere with people’s decision to create families through adoption—simply because of their race—violates their First Amendment freedom of association rights.

Is ICWA’s Differential Treatment Based on Race or Politics?

ICWA obviously treats Indian children and families differently from non-Indian children and families. Whether this is constitutional or not depends on whether it is regarded as race-based or as based on the nature of tribes as political units. In the former case, the distinction would be regarded as suspect, and subjected to strict judicial scrutiny, which it certainly could not survive. But if the distinction is based on political identity rather than race, it is subject only to lenient rational basis review.

In Morton v. Mancari, the Supreme Court upheld the constitutionality of a law that gave preference to Indian tribal members in hiring for positions with the BIA. That preference was “political rather than racial in nature,” the Court held, and therefore did not trigger strict scrutiny, because it “applie[d] only to members of ‘federally recognized’ tribes,” and was “not directed towards a ‘racial’ group consisting of ‘Indians.’”145 Three years later, in United States v. Antelope, the Court relied on Mancari when it upheld a conviction under a criminal statute that differentiated between Indians and non-Indians. As before, the Court noted that the statute was not based on the fact that a person was “racially to be classified as ‘Indian[].’”146 Instead, the parties involved were enrolled members of a tribe, and had committed a crime in Indian country. Thus although Mancari is frequently cited as standing for the proposition that all laws that treat Indians differently from non-Indians are subject to the forgiving standard of rational basis scrutiny, Mancari is actually far narrower than that.

In Rice v. Cayetano. That case involved a Hawaii law whereby only Native Hawaiians could vote for officials of the state’s Office of Native Hawaiian Affairs. It employed a blood quantum requirement among other factors to determine eligibility. The state relied on Mancari to argue that this distinction was political, instead of racial, but the court disagreed. Mancari and its progeny involved laws that singled out “‘a constituency of tribal Indians,’” not “a ‘racial’ group consisting of ‘Indians,’” said the court. The Hawaii law, by contrast, “single[d] out ‘identifiable classes of persons . . . solely because of their ancestry or ethnic characteristics.’” State law even defined the term “Native Hawaiian” as “any descendant of not less than one-half part of the races inhabiting the Hawaiian Islands previous to [European contact] . . . [or] to the descendants of such blood quantum of such aboriginal peoples.” This definition involved factors other than race, but that did not mean it was not a racial classification.147

ICWA plainly falls outside the bounds of Mancari.148 It applies not to members of tribes, but to children who are both eligible for membership and biological children of members.149 Eligibility for tribal membership universally depends on biological ancestry. It follows syllogistically that ICWA applies to a racial group consisting of Indians.150 ICWA’s racial nature is reinforced in various ways, as well. For example, recent BIA regulations and some state laws apply ICWA based on a child being suspected of Indian ancestry, even before tribal status is determined,151 and require state officials to register children for tribal membership if they are eligible.152 ICWA also applies only to children who are both eligible for tribal membership and who are the biological children of members, meaning that a non-Native child adopted by a tribal member is not subject to ICWA, regardless of cultural or political affiliation. Also, other provisions of ICWA, such as the adoption preference granted to “other Indian families” and the foster-care preferences for “an Indian foster home,” expressly apply to the “Indian” race in the abstract, rather than to tribes as specific political entities. Thanks to these provisions, an Alaskan child of Eskimo heritage could be placed with an unrelated member of a Plains Indian tribe in Montana, rather than with a fit, or even fitter, adoptive family of a different race—again, not because of political affiliation, but because of their “Indianness.” The ICWA Penalty Box depends not on membership in a political organization, but on the ethnic quality of being Indian.153

Race was at the forefront of the Supreme Court’s recent decision in Adoptive Couple, which involved a child (known as “Baby Veronica”) whose Cherokee father had surrendered his parental rights before her birth and who had never even met her.154 The mother volunteered the child for adoption by a non-Indian family. After her birth, the father withdrew his consent, and two years later, the South Carolina Supreme Court awarded him custody—all based solely on the fact that the girl had Cherokee blood in her veins. The Supreme Court found this improper. Although it resolved the case on statutory rather than constitutional grounds, it observed that allowing the father to “play his ICWA trump card at the eleventh hour to override the mother’s decision and the child’s best interests . . . solely because an ancestor—even a remote one—was an Indian . . . would raise equal protection concerns.”155

ICWA’s racial nature is sometimes obscured by the fact that factors in addition to race are used in the Act’s definition of “Indian child”—specifically, a child must be both (biologically) eligible for membership, and also the biological child of a tribal member before ICWA can apply.156 This means that, for instance, Sam Houston—an adopted member of the Cherokee tribe157—or Linda Wishkob—the fictional adoptee who plays a critical role in Louise Erdrich’s novel The Round House158—would not have been subject to ICWA despite their complete cultural and social affiliation with their tribes, whereas Lexi or Baby Veronica were subject to ICWA despite lacking any cultural or social connections to a tribe. The deciding factor is genetic.

A racial category does not cease to be a racial category just because factors other than race play a role in defining the class. As the court put it in Rice, “simply because a class defined by ancestry does not include all members of the race does not suffice to make the classification race neutral.”159 After all, the executive order forcing Japanese Americans into detention centers in World War II applied only to persons with more than one-sixteenth Japanese ancestry.160 But the fact that not all persons of Japanese heritage were subject to the order did not make that order anything other than a race-based rule subject to strict scrutiny.161 The law is clear: if race is a but-for factor in the calculus, that calculus is race-based, regardless of the role other factors may play.162

Conclusion

The Indian Child Welfare Act was passed with good intentions: to stop abuses that broke up Indian families and intruded on legitimate tribal government interests. But six of its provisions—jurisdiction transfer, the “active efforts” requirement, the different standards of evidence for foster care decisions and for terminating parental rights, and the preferences applied to foster placement decisions and to adoption cases—place Indian children in a penalty box, depriving them of critical constitutional protections. This applies even to children whose only connection to a tribe is their biological ancestry. The resulting system of legal segregation cannot be reconciled with this nation’s commitments to federalism, equality, and due process of law—or its commitment to the best interests of American Indian children.

 

 

More on this issue

Donate Now

Help all Americans live freer, happier lives. Join the Goldwater Institute as we defend and strengthen freedom in all 50 states.

Donate Now

Since 1988, the Goldwater Institute has been in the liberty business — defending and promoting freedom, and achieving more than 400 victories in all 50 states. Donate today to help support our mission.

We Protect Your Rights

Our attorneys defend individual rights and protect those who cannot protect themselves.

Need Help? Submit a case.

Get Connected to Goldwater

Sign up for the latest news, event updates, and more.